Logical biconditional
In logic and mathematics, the logical biconditional, sometimes known as the material biconditional, is the logical connective used to conjoin two statements and to form the statement " if and only if ", where is known as the antecedent, and the consequent. This is often abbreviated as " iff ". The operator is denoted using a doubleheaded arrow, a prefixed E "Epq", an equality sign, an equivalence sign, or EQV. It is logically equivalent to both and, and the XNOR boolean operator, which means "both or neither".
Semantically, the only case where a logical biconditional is different from a material conditional is the case where the hypothesis is false but the conclusion is true. In which case, the result is true for the conditional, but false for the biconditional.
In the conceptual interpretation, means "All 's are 's and all 's are 's". In other words, the sets and coincide: they are identical. However, this does not mean that and need to have the same meaning. When phrased as a sentence, the antecedent is the subject and the consequent is the predicate of a universal affirmative proposition.
In the propositional interpretation, means that implies and implies ; in other words, the propositions are logically equivalent, in the sense that both are either jointly true or jointly false. Again, this does not mean that they need to have the same meaning, as could be "the triangle ABC has two equal sides" and could be "the triangle ABC has two equal angles". In general, the antecedent is the premise, or the cause, and the consequent is the consequence. When an implication is translated by a hypothetical judgment, the antecedent is called the hypothesis and the consequent is called the thesis.
A common way of demonstrating a biconditional of the form is to demonstrate that and separately. Yet another way of demonstrating the same biconditional is by demonstrating that and.
When both members of the biconditional are propositions, it can be separated into two conditionals, of which one is called a theorem and the other its reciprocal. Thus whenever a theorem and its reciprocal are true, we have a biconditional. A simple theorem gives rise to an implication, whose antecedent is the hypothesis and whose consequent is the thesis of the theorem.
It is often said that the hypothesis is the sufficient condition of the thesis, and that the thesis is the necessary condition of the hypothesis. That is, it is sufficient that the hypothesis be true for the thesis to be true, while it is necessary that the thesis be true if the hypothesis were true. When a theorem and its reciprocal are true, its hypothesis is said to be the necessary and sufficient condition of the thesis. That is, the hypothesis is both the cause and the consequence of the thesis at the same time.
Definition
is an operation on two logical values, typically the values of two propositions, that produces a value of true if and only if both operands are false or both operands are true.Truth table
The following is truth table for :T | T | T |
T | F | F |
F | T | F |
F | F | T |
When more than two statements are involved, combining them with might be ambiguous. For example, the statement
may be interpreted as
or may be interpreted as saying that all are jointly true or jointly false:
As it turns out, these two statements are only the same—when zero or two arguments are involved. In fact, the following truth tables only show the same bit pattern in the line with no argument and in the lines with two arguments:
The left Venn diagram below, and the lines in these matrices represent the same operation.
Venn diagrams
Red areas stand for true.Properties
Commutativity: YesAssociativity: Yes
Distributivity: Biconditional doesn't distribute over any binary function, but logical disjunction distributes over biconditional.
idempotency: No
Monotonicity: No
Truth-preserving: Yes
When all inputs are true, the output is true.
Falsehood-preserving: No
When all inputs are false, the output is not false.
Walsh spectrum:
Nonlinearity: 0
Rules of inference
Like all connectives in first-order logic, the biconditional has rules of inference that govern its use in formal proofs.Biconditional introduction
Biconditional introduction allows one to infer that if B follows from A and A follows from B, then A if and only if B.For example, from the statements "if I'm breathing, then I'm alive" and "if I'm alive, then I'm breathing", it can be inferred that "I'm breathing if and only if I'm alive" or equivalently, "I'm alive if and only if I'm breathing." Or more schematically:
B → A
A → B
∴ A ↔ B
B → A
A → B
∴ B ↔ A
Biconditional elimination
Biconditional elimination allows one to infer a conditional from a biconditional: if A ↔ B is true, then one may infer either A → B, or B → A.For example, if it is true that I'm breathing if and only if I'm alive, then it's true that if I'm breathing, then I'm alive; likewise, it's true that if I'm alive, then I'm breathing. Or more schematically:
A ↔ B
∴ A → B
A ↔ B
∴ B → A
Colloquial usage
One unambiguous way of stating a biconditional in plain English is to adopt the form "b if a and a if b"—if the standard form "a if and only if b" is not used. Slightly more formally, one could also say that "b implies a and a implies b", or "a is necessary and sufficient for b". The plain English "if'" may sometimes be used as a biconditional. In which case, one must take into consideration the surrounding context when interpreting these words.For example, the statement "I'll buy you a new wallet if you need one" may be interpreted as a biconditional, since the speaker doesn't intend a valid outcome to be buying the wallet whether or not the wallet is needed. However, "it is cloudy if it is raining" is generally not meant as a biconditional, since it can still be cloudy even if it is not raining.